Ben Lerner, The Hatred of Poetry (2016)
Elegant and substantive recent essay.
From the title and the tone, Lerner suggests
that the questions he addresses pertain to poetry in general (and hence to
humanity in general), however his discussion addresses the Anglo, and more
specifically American, poetic tradition and the current political debate in the
US.
This tradition is made to be speaking for
poetry in general. Even though Lerner himself discusses at length what is at
stake in pretending to speak for everyone, he replicates this tension. While
including voices that are often said to be suppressed in the United States, his
discussion is distinctively restricted to the forms and political questions of
this country.
As such, his essay can be approached
ethnographically: an anthropology of poetry reads these declarations as a
symptom to understand what are the ideas about poetry that circulate currently
in the US.
Lerner’s essay is organized around a
distinction between Poetry with a capital P and the concrete poems that humans
write. This distinction seems to come from the writings of A. Grossman, a
literary critic and poet to whom Lerner is indebted (the essay reads like a
dialogue with Grossman, or an eulogy for his passing).
For Lerner, Poetry with a capital P is an
idea: the desire humans have “to reach the transcendent or divine” (p.8) –the
desire to go beyond the historical, the finite, the actual. Concrete poems are
the realizations of this desire, and as such are destined to fail. They cannot
“reach” beyond, and are inevitably hated for this reason (by everyone,
including Lerner, and other readers of poetry—one senses here that part of this
hatred is self-loathing). Bad poets realize this failure literally, good poets
(Keats, Dickinson, Whitman, Rankine) have different strategies to inhabit this
failure as part of the act of poetic composition itself.
The essay operates via an explicit platonic
logic that juxtaposes the idea (perfection, infinity, universality, eternity)
of Poetry and its human realization (imperfection, finitude, particularity,
history) in concrete poems. This is also inevitably, a theological argument
about humans and the divine. God is impossible to reach, and yet humans strive
to attain it (comprehend it, inhabit it, say it apophatically, see below).
To differentiate between the divine and the
human order and their relationship, Lerner often uses the terms virtual and actual:
virtual poetry and actual poems. It is unclear to me if this is a reference to
the Bergson/Deleuze trajectory. Possibly, but the relationship that Lerner
establishes between the two orders is distinctively different from B/D. Whereas
in the B/D trajectory (especially in Deleuze via Spinoza – though there are
certainly platonic echoes here as well) the virtual and the actual stand in a
relationship of “expression,” Lerner seems to favor an argument about the
impossibility of reconciling two parallel orders, where failure is the only
possible relationship between an idea and its reconciliation. One cannot reach
perfection, only possibly expressing this failure in good concrete poems that
might appear “perfect” or at least fulfilling, only in retrospect.
In Lerner’s pages the idea that humans are
fallible, somewhat lacking completion looms large: actual poems try to
articulate what cannot be articulated and they work best when they express this
impossibility to express.
[Interestingly, here Lerner seems to say
something similar to Butler on performativity, even though for Lerner the
question seems less about the idea of a fractured (psycho-analytically)
un-reconciled self, and more about a theologically inflected paradise lost.
There is a touch of psychoanalysis in Lerner, but so rarefied that it turns
Freud into a theologian, and the “desire to transcend” is never quite unpacked.
Lerner’s lack (of perfection and transcendence) is also quite unlike Lacan’s in
that it is not strictly unsayable: in fact this is what “good” poets do all the
time, it is all they can do, state the impossibility of saying what they are
saying].
Lerner seems to be missing an intermediary--
“modal”-- passage whereby the infinitude of God/Poetry is turned into an
existence into actual concrete instantiation. Reading concrete poems as signs
of failure, he seems to deny the instantiation of what it is, and in someway
reduce the “power of poetry” to a via negativa (=to evoke what cannot be
evoked, to say what God is only by stating what is not).
In other words, Lerner seems to suggest
that there is a difference between the idea and its expression in concrete
poems. The expression seems to only takes place after the idea is already
formed, this is why in certain passages he describes this process as one of
“objectification” (from the point of view of the poet) or “identification”
(from the point of view of the reader). Hence a model that (contrary to its
theological underpinning and its debt to psychoanalysis) seems to be predicated
on the idea of a stable unified self, guided by an internal cognition (or
experience) which is then “expressed” in a movement from the inside to the
outside: the autonomous, conscious individual. [This is not spelled exactly in
these terms, but I feel that many elements point in this direction, even if at
times Lerner interjects other trajectories that leave more room for alternative
readings such as on Dickinson.]
In his discussion of Dickinson and the
materiality of her poems (the fantastic envelopes) Lerner seems to undo part of
his own “idealistic” argumentation by foregrounding the notion that the idea of
poetry itself is retrospective in relation to the writing – but then seems to
retract this trajectory by claiming that Dickinson’s is yet another strategy to
defy the impossible demands of Poetry: in other words the “call to transcend”
preceeds any poetic engagement.
After having discussed Keats and Dickinson,
and having somewhat neutralized the political pretensions of the “avant-guarde”
(Futurists) to erase the question of Poetry/poems, Lerner goes himself
“political” (with a light touch) in discussing Whitman. Here the failure of
poems is linked with the failure of American democracy, or rather the failure
of Whitman’s pretense to turn the self into a multitude, the I into a you-we.
Lerner seems to suggest that Whitman “succeeded” in articulating Poetry via his
concrete poems, but that the “Poetry” of his politics has miserably failed in
retrospect (so is this rather different from his argument above?).
Lerner concludes that what poetry can do is
to highlight current racial violence and impossibility of reconciliation by
highlighting racial fissures as for example in the writings of C. Rankine who
enacts depersonalization via prose that evokes the loss of poetry [there
follows an interesting discussion of the sign / “virgule” in contemporary
American poetry].
Politics here is mostly an affair of
“identification.” Notable in this discussion is the analysis of pronouns :I,
you, we-- as if what matters is to identify who you are/who am I. This view of
politics culminates in an idea of the person as the supreme enactment of Poetry
(“…a person is someone who can find consciousness shareable through poetry” p
77) and the counterpoint to a sense of community. So one finds here the
politico-theological paradigm discussed by Esposito deployed in its fullness. There
seems to be an empasse here. An empasse that might reflect the current state of
political discussions in the US.
Denis Tedlock has already addressed the
partition between poetry and prose, which in Lerner’s case would be the one
between Poetry and concrete poems. See my post on Tedlock.
Towards the end of the essay, Lerner starts
to use the expression “virtual poem.” This also seems to go beyond his own
assertions above, recognizing that there are indeed concrete poems that can
“reach beyond” – what or who decides when a poem is virtual?
How does not talk
about the power of poetry ?
Interestingly, Lerner’s answer seems to be
that this can only happen via poetry itself. The last few pages of the essay
(78-86) diverge from the terse argumentation of the preceding sections and move
toward a more exploratory terrain, more personal but also more lyrical. It is
prose, but --as Lerner has suggested through out-- it is in prose (as a
negation of the failure of concrete poems) that Poetry can find its place, in
poems that are virtually rather than actually so. Here the act of naming the
world mixes with reminiscences of the awe and the sublime (hypermarkets and
movie theaters as site of primordial experience). Even though the mantra of the
essay is repeated once more-- “there is no need to go on multiplying examples
of an impulse that can produce no adequate examples – of a capacity that can’t
be objectified without falsification” (85)—one senses that now this has become
a solid rhetorical figure Apophasis
or preterition. A place of possibility of love, as the last sentence suggests
with poetic elegance.
Though Lerner puts the collective at the
center of his “political” reflections, and writes at length about the civic
potential of poetry (he does not use the word civic, though it is evoked
throughout, as for example in Withman or in Rankine’s piece titled Citizen), he seems to avoid the
narrative, fabulative dimension of poetry. After all Plato’s concern with
poetry, as Lerner notes, was the preoccupation that poets feed the imagination
(as opposed to the truth of philosophy).
There is no discussion of myth, of the
relevance of poetry as a sense making (or unmaking) narrative. This is probably
a symptom of the current US political climate in which narrative itself cannot
be but evoked in terms of failure (and this is what Lerner implicitly suggests,
though on the other hand he seems quite straightforward in his own political
narrative which could be labeled mannerist).
On the margin:
It would be interesting to juxtapose
Lerner’s approach to one inflected by Vico, as both discuss poetry in relation
to theology but in quite different directions. I am not referring here only to those
who read Vico in relation to his “civic” theory (the New Science as a “reasoned civic theology” in which poetry plays a
central role). Rather it might be useful to think about Vico’s idea that poetic
knowledge, a human necessity, provides self-sustaining narratives to make sense
of the world. It might be that this is only a reversal of Lerner’s statement
that poetry is by default apophatic (it can only say what it is not). But in
Vico this is a statement of fact, of necessity: poetic (i.e. non scientific)
discourse emerges as a necessity of being in the world, it is not an effort to
“reach beyond it” but to make sense of it (an empirical desire if you wish—a
desire that is linked to animality and naturality but also to the need for
communication). So poetry is not a “place of possibility” but the imperfect,
rough outcome of a necessity (as desire is a necessity). Vico’s empiricism
displaces Lerner’s idealism and locates desire in necessity rather than
transcendence.
Comments
Post a Comment